Monday, 9 July 2012

Levinas, Ethics and the Encounter with an Art Object



In order to look at the issue of the possibility of the ‘ethical’ encounter with an art object a logical starting point is the work of Emmanuel Levinas. Rather than metaphysical ontology, Levinas maintained that ethics was the ‘first philosophy’ as it was the interaction with the ‘Other’ that gave meaning to our existence. Levinas’ work, beginning with the Totality and Infinity (1961) is a critique of Western philosophy, in particular Heidegger and Husserl. Levinas’ concern is that Western philosophy has been preoccupied with Being and the self, at the expense of what is otherwise than Being, what lies outside the self as infinite and alterior, the Other. The term ‘Other’ can also be found in the work of Hegel who introduced it as an important part of self-consciousness1.

Levinas discusses the possibility of the ethical encounter with the ‘Other’ and places particular importance on the face-to-face relationship between it and the self. Being face-to-face with the Other forbids a reduction to sameness and simultaneously creates a responsibility for the other in the self. As human beings we are not inherently ethical, with our most primal desire being to kill the other and remove the threat of the unknown, as Hegel puts in Phenomenology of Spirit (1977) ‘each consciousness pursues the death of the other’2. Levinas argues that by putting ourselves face-to-face with the other we are unable to carry out this desire, as by turning to face the Other we are acknowledging their demand of ‘thou shalt not kill me’. We should hold the belief that we are all responsible for all others but I (the self) am more responsible than all others. In accordance with Levinas the Other is superior or prior to the self and the mere presence of the Other makes demands before one can respond by either helping or ignoring them. At this point, one may draw parallels between these moral concerns and that of the Bible, ‘turning the other cheek’ being of particular relevance.

For Levinas, the Other is always unknowable and cannot be made into an object of the self. There is inherent asymmetry to the Other: the Other is and shall always remain ‘other’. In attempting to appropriate and grasp the character of the Other we are in a sense killing it, ceasing to allow it to exist as other. Gwendolyn Bays (1948) puts it rather succinctly when she writes ‘in understanding my friend's mind I must first "freeze" it, encompass it, and in this sense kill it’3. She writes this in reference to Simone de Beauvoir’s novel L'Invitee (1943) (often translated as ‘She Came to Stay’) which charts the relationship of Pierre and Francoise (widely accepted to be a thinly veiled representation of Beauvior herself and Jean-Paul Satre) and the damaged caused by a young girl named Xaviere who threatens to break them apart. The character of Francoise can choose to exile Xaviere or take her under her wing, and it is by her ‘adoption of Xaviere (that) she had pursued the younger girl's death, and her generous acceptance of Xaviere's competition had itself been a strategy of containment.’4

Another important element to make reference to in the work of Levinas is the differentiation that is made between the act of ‘saying’ and the ‘said’. The two are distinguished in that the ‘saying’ is irreducible to one meaning and infinite, it is the act of communication, whereas the ‘said’ is what is conveyed in the saying and can is normally reduced to something finite (there is obviously the potential for misinterpretation but this is of little consequence). In short, it is the act of communication that is more important than the information that is being communicated. The act of paying attention to the ‘saying’ is ethical in that it shows non-indifference to the Other, regardless of what is being ‘said’. The ‘said’ is potentially of little relevance, it is allowing the Other the opportunity to say that is our responsibility, not interpreting and making assessments of the ‘said’. An example, which allows us to relate to this, is perhaps that of banal conversation. It is the act of engaging with someone, of acknowledging them and allowing them the time and space to speak to us that is of importance, not the content of the day-to-day pleasantries that are being exchanged. It is the act of friendship, not the comments about the weather that are meaningful in such a scenario.

Now let us expand upon this idea of the ethical encounter. If we take the concept of the Other to mean not just the rest of mankind but in fact to all objects that are outside ourselves, and move away from the idea of the encounter as being a social one, could we perhaps apply the idea of the ethical encounter to the encounter with an art object, with the art object as the ‘Other’? Let us look at how such an application might work. Initially it could be said that any attempt to be face-to-face with the art object, to acknowledge its’ attempt at ‘saying’ is the basis for an ethical encounter. By allowing it to make demands of us (our time, turning and facing it) we are allowing the art object to be prior to ourselves, which Levinas suggests, is ethically sound. So far, so good. This however, is rarely the extent of our encounter with the art object. There is undeniably, consciously or otherwise an attempt on the viewer’s part to make sense of the meaning of a piece of work, an attempt to decipher the ‘said’, to draw conclusions about the status of the object as ‘other’.

If we are to agree with Levinas, then surely this is the making of an unethical encounter, attempting to conceive the other and take it on as a part of the self. Expecting to leave an encounter with an art object with a coherent understanding of what it is that has been ‘said’ is effectively destroying it’s ‘otherness’. Not only this, but upon assessing what we believe to have been ‘said’ we make judgements as to the competency of the ‘saying’. It is also true to say that on occasion, we may deny an art object a face-to-face encounter because of what we believe the content of the said to be. If we believe that a work may be offensive or irrelevant, we may decide to avoid seeing it, denying it the potential of saying. On occasion we may turn away from a work that we deem unworthy of our time, in which case are we not shying away from Levinas’ plea that we must be responsible for the Other more than the Other must be responsible for us? We are punishing the Other for not giving us what we hoped it might, this itself cannot be seen to be ethical, nor can imposing limits upon it’s worth and value. Perhaps then the most ethical way to encounter an art object is to ask nothing of the object, to expect to learn nothing and place the importance on the fact that the art object is ‘saying’ something, regardless of what that is. However, if we were to function in such a manner then surely no art work could be held as being of higher merit than any other, that fact that an art object was ‘saying’ something, regardless of how banal would be enough for it to be heralded as worthy of our time. While this may seem an ethical practice, it seems deeply counterintuitive and potentially rather destructive. If all work was to deemed of the same merit, what would be the incentive to create something truly exceptional. Levinas, it seems, is already causing us problems.

If we take this idea, potentially unwisely, yet further, could it be said that by hailing an art object as one of artistic merit we are making premature assumptions of its’ meaning and worth? This could be seen as an example of placing too much emphasis on the ‘said’ than on the ‘saying’. We are placing upon it our own pre-existing expectation that it will have some meaningful content or contribution higher than alternative objects or Others. Perhaps in differentiating between an object and an art object we are claiming to know something definitive about the ‘unknowable’, in which case our encounter becomes unethical as soon as we ascribe the label ‘art’. We believe that a painting will have something more relevant to tell us than a table, so the painting is placed in a specially designed space and the table is reduced to a servant, forgotten under a pile of papers and coffee mugs. What is the solution, do we spend our time having ‘encounters’ with tables, or should we use ‘David with the Head of Goliath’5 as a handy place to balance a beverage?

If we are to extrapolate (somewhat uncompromisingly perhaps) Levinas’ ideas into the world of art we seem to be at risk of writing off criticism, theory and curation and any encounter with an art object as inherently unethical. A critic should not make any judgements about a piece of work, because one Other should surely not be held in higher regard than another. Art Theory could be seen as trying to make claims about the otherness of Other, and in doing so the Other is destroyed and effectively killed, leading us into deeply unethical territory. Curating an exhibition is making claims as to knowledge of otherness and of the ‘said’ as being meaningful in some way and worthy of the title of ‘art’. So what is the answer, do we allow Levinas’ ethics to chip away at the foundation of art appreciation and criticism?

There seem to be two possible ways to escape from the bind into which Levinas, his ethics and this line of enquiry seem to have placed us. Firstly we may choose to reassess the relationship we should expect to have with the Other and question whether asymmetry really is the most ethical relationship to expect to have. Zizek’s ‘Neighbor and Other Monsters’(2005)6 leads us to look at symmetry in a slightly different way. If asymmetry leads us to always be more responsible for the Other than they are for us, we are placing ourselves in a privileged position. We are claiming to be the ones with moral responsibility, which could be seen as claiming to be the higher being. Further to this point, surely an ethical relationship with the Other should rely upon a balance of equality, with equal responsibility on both sides and a free exchange of ideas and knowledge. One could argue that the ethical way to encounter the Other is by engaging from a level playing field and recognising the shared experience we have with the Other who exists within the same time and space as us. This could lead us into difficulty again however as it would be hard to claim this is the relationship we have with an art object, while we may expect to gain something from our encounter with an art object, one cannot reasonably claim that the art object gains anything from us.

The second route to take perhaps to abandon the idea that an encounter with an art object must necessarily be ethical. Let us cast an eye over the life of an art object. In the creation of a work in the first place an artist is claiming to have something of relevance to say, something that we need to hear. Surely these potential delusions of grandeur are not particularly ethical and could be, (in fact often are) judged to be misplaced. Questions could be asked as to how ethically sound it is for one to self-appoint as someone whose voice should be more loudly heard than that of others’, surely this is not placing the demands of the Other as prior to the self.

The subject matter of an art work is another topic in which ethical considerations come into play. An often contentious issue is that of nudity and sexual explicit content, where the line falls between art and pornography, if indeed there is one. An example of a casualty of such debate is a photograph by Nan Goldin that was part of her ‘Thanksgiving’ series, which was seized by police after the image of a naked child was deemed ‘pornographic’ and potentially criminal7. Ethical issues are by no means confined to the subject matter of a work of art, the way in which such work has been created does not escape scrutiny. Austrian artist Valie Export was trialed in 1977 for cruelty to animals after tying a bird to a perch and pouring hot wax over it as part of a performance8.

Other areas of the ‘art world’ can hardly be seen to be entirely ethical, the cut throat world of art business is surely one that cannot be said to be always ruled by ethical and moral ideals. The selling and acquiring of works is sure to have winner and losers. In March of this year New York based art dealer Lawrence Salander pleaded guilty to grand larceny and fraud after admitting to selling artworks he didn’t own up the value of $120 million, little of which is expected to be recovered9. If this is the background to the object we encounter, it seems to me that to expect that encounter to be a purely ethical one may be a little naïve, or at least a little idealistic. To place the confines of ethicality on an artwork, as we perhaps limiting its potential of ‘saying’?

Also, in engaging with an encounter with an art object it is fair to say that we are already expecting something of it. The relationship will always be a little one sided, we have nothing to offer it, aside from our attention and yet we are anticipating that it will be able to do something remarkable for us. We hope that it will convey some truth, uncover a secret or hand us some precious wisdom or insight and ask for little in return. This is potentially unethical, yes, but to make the demand that we abandon these expectations in order to restore our ethics seems to be to destroy the encounter itself.

Perhaps it is that Levinas is potentially the ideal, an existence in which we have no prejudicial ideas. No expectations exist of a person or object or our encounter with either and we continue to respect the idea that the Other will remain ‘other’. This instinctively is a aspiration for the social encounter, to not expect anything from another person, to not wish to reduce their differences into something that we can understand and conceive, although this could be potentially lonely existence. One in which we do not expect anything from anyone else and all moral responsibility falls at our feet. While it may be wrong to try to fully conceive the Other, our relationship with the Other seems important in order to be able to gain anything from our encounter with it. To attempt to extrapolate this in regards to the encounter with an art object does not seem to be a workable example. If the Other was always the unknown, and works of art were seen as the Other, then art, literature music and indeed the rest of mankind would be able to teach us nothing, and to allow it to would be to destroy it. We would be left unmoved and mystified by any such encounter and even if it is supposedly ethical, it doesn’t seem to be in any way desirable.

Maybe it is wrong to be looking to have an ethical encounter with such an object. Perhaps the ethical encounter should have no more pre-requisites than that we allow ourselves to give time to the art object, that we allow it to do it’s saying. Whether we manage to grasp the ‘said’ is hugely subjective, some work will shout at us, others will whisper quietly in a language that is barely decipherable, and there are some that will remain mute. It is my belief that the most rewarding encounter with an artwork shocks us, haunts us, unsettles us and disrupts us, and where does one begin to look for the ethical in that?
1 Hegel, G. W. F. (1977) Phenomenology of spirit. Trans. A. V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
2 Hegel, G. W. F. (1977). Phenomenology of spirit. Trans. A. V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (pp. 113)
3 Bays, G. (1948) Simone de Beauvoir: Ethics and art, Yale French Studies, vol. 1, pp. 107.
4 Bays, G. (1948) Simone de Beauvoir: Ethics and art, Yale French Studies, vol. 1, pp. 108.
5 Caravaggio, M. M. (1609-1610) David with the Head of Goliath [Painting]. Galleria Borghese, Rome.
6 Zizek, S. (2005) ‘The neighbor and other monsters’, in Zizek, L., Slanter, E. L and Reinhard, K. The Neighbor: Three Inquiries in Political Theology, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
8 http://viennanet.info/polemics/valie-export-in-belvedere [14 Nov 2010]
9 http://www.timesonline.co.uk/tol/news/world/us_and_americas/article5983268.ece [14 Nov 2010]

No comments:

Post a Comment